Wednesday, December 10, 2014
Conversation with Stanislas Dehaene
Catherine in conversation with Stanislas Dehaene on consciousness:
https://www.dropbox.com/s/4fm5nnfye6msydb/Malabou%20Dehaene.pdf?dl=0
https://www.dropbox.com/s/4fm5nnfye6msydb/Malabou%20Dehaene.pdf?dl=0
Friday, December 5, 2014
Relinquishing the Transcendental? (audio)
The audio of Catherine's talk, "Relinquishing the Transcendental? Speculative Realism in Question" in London (4 December 2014):
http://backdoorbroadcasting.net/2014/12/catherine-malabou-relinquishing-the-transcendental-speculative-realism-in-question/
Thanks to Daniel Felstead for the link.
http://backdoorbroadcasting.net/2014/12/catherine-malabou-relinquishing-the-transcendental-speculative-realism-in-question/
Thanks to Daniel Felstead for the link.
Wednesday, December 3, 2014
Review of Adrian Johnston's Adventures in Transcendental Materialism
John Protevi reviews Adrian Johnston's Adventures in Transcendental Materialism: Dialogues with Contemporary Thinkers at NDPR:
http://ndpr.nd.edu/news/54506-adventures-in-transcendental-materialism-dialogues-with-contemporary-thinkers/
"With regard to science, the key division here is that Johnston thinks biology rather than quantum physics, as with Žižek, offers the best scientific grounding for transcendental materialism (16). (The relation to science is also among the points that divide Johnston from Badiou and Malabou. While Johnston's preference for the life sciences distinguishes him from the mathematically oriented Badiou, he agrees with Malabou that neuroscience is the key science. However, Malabou thinks the findings of neuroscience outstrip the ability of psychoanalysis to deal with real neuronal/subjective destruction, while Johnston thinks a properly reformatted psychoanalysis retains some utility even there".
http://ndpr.nd.edu/news/54506-adventures-in-transcendental-materialism-dialogues-with-contemporary-thinkers/
"With regard to science, the key division here is that Johnston thinks biology rather than quantum physics, as with Žižek, offers the best scientific grounding for transcendental materialism (16). (The relation to science is also among the points that divide Johnston from Badiou and Malabou. While Johnston's preference for the life sciences distinguishes him from the mathematically oriented Badiou, he agrees with Malabou that neuroscience is the key science. However, Malabou thinks the findings of neuroscience outstrip the ability of psychoanalysis to deal with real neuronal/subjective destruction, while Johnston thinks a properly reformatted psychoanalysis retains some utility even there".
Tuesday, November 11, 2014
The New Realism (Paris, December)
Catherine will be speaking in Paris on December 6 with Graham Harman, Mario De Caro, Sarah De Sanctis, Tristan Garcia, Cathérine Malabou, and Vincenzo Santarcangelo.
The location is the EHESS, and the occasion is the publication in French of Maurizio Ferraris’ Manifesto of New Realism
For the conference program, click here: https://doctorzamalek2.files.wordpress.com/2014/11/noveauxrealisme_ehess_2014.pdf
Between Dialectics and Deconstruction: An Interview
"Between Dialectics and Deconstruction: An Interview with Catherine Malabou" by Mark Rainey with images by Emily Speed in Nyx: A Noctournal
http://www.scribd.com/doc/241224000/Nyx-a-noctournal-8-Skin
http://www.scribd.com/doc/241224000/Nyx-a-noctournal-8-Skin
Friday, November 7, 2014
Love in the Post Interview
The screenplay of Martin McQuillan and Joanna Callaghan's film Love in the Post plus essays and interviews including "Cinema is Not a Brain Reading" an interview conducted with Catherine Malabou in the Jardin du Luxembourg, Paris in September 2012
http://www.rowmaninternational.com/books/love-in-the-post-from-plato-to-derrida
Thursday, November 6, 2014
What Remains: Of Glas (New York, 14 November)
Friday, November 14th, 1:30 p.m. -6:30 p.m.
What Remains: Of Glas
The Modern & Contemporary Colloquium is excited to host a workshop exploring Jacques Derrida's playful, dizzying Glas. Speakers include:
Catherine Malabou (Kingston University, London), “Philosophy in Erection”
Geoffrey Bennington (Emory University, currently Visiting Professor, NYU), “Method and Metaphor in Derrida's Glas”
Martin McQuillan (Kingston University, London), “Derrida Amongst the Palestinians”
Simon Morgan-Wortham (Kingston University, London), “Fleeced”
Tina Chanter (Kingston University), "Antigone, Hegel, Derrida"
Juliet Fleming (NYU), Closing Remarks
Catherine Malabou (Kingston University, London), “Philosophy in Erection”
Geoffrey Bennington (Emory University, currently Visiting Professor, NYU), “Method and Metaphor in Derrida's Glas”
Martin McQuillan (Kingston University, London), “Derrida Amongst the Palestinians”
Simon Morgan-Wortham (Kingston University, London), “Fleeced”
Tina Chanter (Kingston University), "Antigone, Hegel, Derrida"
Juliet Fleming (NYU), Closing Remarks
Location: Event Space
244 Greene St.
244 Greene St.
Thursday, October 23, 2014
Wednesday, October 22, 2014
Susan Kealy's Dissertation on Malabou + Del Toro
Here is a link to a first class B.A disseration by Susan Kealy (IADT, Dublin) on Malabou's new wounded and trauma in the films of Guillermo Del Toro especially Pan's Labyrinth:
https://www.dropbox.com/s/pbd1u0oljx7rl1e/2Memory%20and%20Trauma%20in%20Guillermo%20del%20Toro%20FULL%20DISSERTATION.docx?dl=0
https://www.dropbox.com/s/pbd1u0oljx7rl1e/2Memory%20and%20Trauma%20in%20Guillermo%20del%20Toro%20FULL%20DISSERTATION.docx?dl=0
Monday, October 13, 2014
Sunday, September 14, 2014
Sunday, August 31, 2014
New book on Malabou and Deleuze & Guattari
Gabriel Schenker has a new book out called Organic Texture (Atropos Press) staging a dialogue between Malabou's plasticity and Deleuze and Guattari's organic strata.
Here is the description:
What would happen to Deleuze and Guattari's organic strata and body without organs if they were to have been constructed not in relation to the geneticism of the sixties but to the epigenetic field that boomed in the 2000's? This work starts from a reconfiguration of the organic basis of their theory which, in dialogue with epigenetics, neuroscience, and the work of Catherine Malabou, leads to a new understanding of the organism. The organism is no longer a fixed and hierarchical prison keeping us from exploring our potentials but a texture weaved between cells and emotions, bodies and discourses, individuals and groups, organic and inorganic. No longer a stratic reality to be repressed but the very basis of our life potentials.
http://www.amazon.com/Organic-Texture-Gabriel-Schenker/dp/1940813190
Here is the description:
What would happen to Deleuze and Guattari's organic strata and body without organs if they were to have been constructed not in relation to the geneticism of the sixties but to the epigenetic field that boomed in the 2000's? This work starts from a reconfiguration of the organic basis of their theory which, in dialogue with epigenetics, neuroscience, and the work of Catherine Malabou, leads to a new understanding of the organism. The organism is no longer a fixed and hierarchical prison keeping us from exploring our potentials but a texture weaved between cells and emotions, bodies and discourses, individuals and groups, organic and inorganic. No longer a stratic reality to be repressed but the very basis of our life potentials.
http://www.amazon.com/Organic-Texture-Gabriel-Schenker/dp/1940813190
Tuesday, July 1, 2014
Wednesday, June 25, 2014
Sunday, June 22, 2014
London Graduate School Summer Academy on Derrida's Glas
The final programme for the London Graduate School Summer Academy to be held at Central Saint MartinsFor m has now been announced and is as follows:
Derrida’s Glas
Final Programme
Monday 23rd June
9-9.30 Registration
9.30-10 Welcome and introduction
10-12 Mairéad Hanrahan (University College London), ‘Mourning Taxonomies’
2-4 Reading groups, led by Mairéad Hanrahan and Simon Morgan Wortham
4.30pm Social event
Tuesday 24th June
10-12 Catherine Malabou (Kingston University), ‘Philosophy in Erection’
2-4 Reading groups, led by Catherine Malabou and Andrew Benjamin
4-6 Etienne Balibar (Columbia University/Kingston University), ‘Community, Universality, and the différance of the Absolute in Glas’
Wednesday 25th June
10-12 Tina Chanter (Kingston University), ‘Antigone as White Fetish of Hegel and Seductress of Derrida’
2-4 Reading groups, led by Tina Chanter and Chiara Alfano
Thursday 26th June
10-12 Geoffrey Bennington (Emory University), ‘Method and Metaphor in Glas’
2-4 Reading groups, led by Geoffrey Bennington and Chiara Alfano
4-6 Andrew Benjamin (Kingston University/Monash University), ‘Où conduit le désir d’Antigone? Derrida, Antigone’
Close
Theater, Performance, Philosophy Conference 2014: Crossings and Transfers in Contemporary Anglo-American Thought
Theater, Performance, Philosophy Conference 2014: Crossings and Transfers in Contemporary Anglo-American Thought, June 26 – 28, 2014 at the University of Paris-Sorbonne. The keynote lecturers are Judith Butler, Alphonso Lingis, Catherine Malabou, Jon McKenzie, Martin Puchner and Avital Ronell.
http://tpp2014.com/en-us/plenaries/
Read the introduction to Malabou's work "Catherine Malabou and the Concept of Plasticity" by Maite Marciano and Anna Street here: http://tpp2014.com/catherine-malabou-concept-plasticity/
http://tpp2014.com/en-us/plenaries/
Read the introduction to Malabou's work "Catherine Malabou and the Concept of Plasticity" by Maite Marciano and Anna Street here: http://tpp2014.com/catherine-malabou-concept-plasticity/
Wednesday, June 18, 2014
New Translation: "The Ungraspable in Question, or to Catch Oneself Dying"
The Ungraspable in Question, or to Catch
Oneself Dying
Catherine Malabou
Translated by Simona Rowen
Jacques Derrida’s thought requires that we open ourselves
to it through what is ungraspable in
us, through that which in us, hesitates precisely to say «us », through
that which, in us, and beyond any unconscious economy, is the secret of us in
us, the unexpectedness of any subject, incalculable and unforeseeable.
In a word, the event. One of the only «definitions », that Derrida agrees to give of deconstruction is: « “Deconstruction, is at bottom what occurs[1].» This
opening to the event, to the occurrence of the wholly other, is exactly that
which, in deconstruction, is ungraspable,
in other terms un-deconstructable. Since
it is impossible to calculate or to foresee the effects of deconstruction, any
encounter with it is a case,
beginning therefore with the event of the «us» in us,
which strikes subjectivity by surprise.
The event can be the fortunate surprise, luck. Yet it can also be the worst, catastrophe,
destruction, or ruin. This is why it is
impossible to think the event otherwise than by examining the relationship to
death, knowing that there is never « the death», but more than one death in death.
More than one death. This strange assertion is without a doubt
one of the most radical and most important of Derrida’s thought. It is present from the first texts. Indeed one reads in « La Mythologie
Blanche»: «As soon
as there is more than one death, the problem of death complicates itself
infinitely[2].» There is
always more than one death, and this motif of plural death persists more and
more in the oeuvre, to the point of imposing itself today, if one takes into
consideration the most recent works, as the most delicate point, that is to say
at once the most manifest and the most complex, of deconstruction. Its limit-assertion, once could say.
Indeed, to draw out a plurality of deaths in death, to see in it a mobile
multiplicity, which do not gather together, which do not synthesize, but remain
infinitely and aporetically open, is truly to deal the fatal blow to subjectivity, thus to metaphysics, but also to a
certain «Destruktion» of metaphysics, that is to say to Heideggerian
thought. Dasein, being-towards-death, though it is not a subject,
nevertheless remains, according to Derrida, a site which obscures the plurality
of death, a moment of collection, of
unification, and thus of resoluteness.
To assert «more than
one death» is truly
to situate, outside of metaphysics and the deconstruction of metaphysics, the
place of the ungraspable. How might we
designate more precisely the non-subjectivizable, the incomprehensible, the
un-anticipatable, the very eventementality of the event?
I will turn, in order to make right on the phrase «more than one death», to Derrida’s text entitled «Demeure, Athènes», which bears the subtitle: «We owe ourselves to death [Nous nous devons à la mort][3].» This text accompanies a series of
photographs of Athens taken by Jean-François Bonhomme. It offers a reflection, the word is of importance, on photography, death, and
event. It specifically makes appear, as
a developer [révélateur] would the deaths within death, it offers an arresting view
on this
plurality. It would require much time to
do justice to such pluralization. I will
make do with drawing out four main motifs at work in this thanatography. Four deaths within death, each of them
finding itself differentiated in its turn, and this always on the basis of a
declension of the verb «prendre», «to take», which accompanies the different
significations of the initial phrase:
«We owe ourselves to death». Let
us watch Derrida foretell and read the deaths of Athens.
These four motifs are, firstly, death understood as stratification of the archive, or as paradoxical condition of survival. Secondly,
as delaying device, as a final notice
or ordinance of having to live, Thirdly, death as anticipation of deadline. Fourthly,
death and the question of the dissociation of «us».
First motif. Derrida
insists on the fact that Athens is a city «which died more than once, in
several times[4] ». A city
that comprehends its different
deaths, which inscribes its own mourning within it. In light of the photographs that he
considers, Derrida shows how Athens owes itself triply to death:
As a matter of debt or of necessity, as a matter of economy,
as a matter of the «marketplace», the
landscape of these streets, these cafés, these markets, these musical
instruments, will have to die. It is the law. They are threatened by death or promised to
death: three deaths, three instances, three temporalities of death from the
point of view of the photographer: the first before the shot, the second through
the shot, the last much later still, for another day, but it is imminent, after the appearance of the print.[5]
These deaths and these plural times, which
refer to the stratums of the city’s memory, to the stratification of the
archive called Athens, appear at the same time as conditions of the survival of
Athens. «Athens is a city which died
more than once, in several times […] a city busy keeping a close watch over its
disruptions, but […] a living city[6].» Athens’ sepulchral monumentality, which
destines and designs it to interiorize and save the lost, is therefore at the
same time an injunction to transformation, to reconstruction, to the opening of
an incalculable, an ungraspable deferral, life which continues.
However, as soon as it is discovered, as soon as it is
glimpsed, this deferral, which owes its paradoxical possibility to several
integrated deaths, to several interiorizations, to several accomplished griefs,
fades, it does not gather together, it unfastens
[se déprend]. Indeed, the very
concept of grief on which it rests, grief as incorporation and interiorization
of the lost, this grief which is death in life but also the survival of life,
quavers, hesitates, lets the other in it speak.
Athens owes itself to death, we owe ourselves to death… in
order to survive, but this survival is never guarantied. Any archive, as is shown in particular in the
text «No Apocalypse, not now»
included in Psyché, is always and in
principle threatened by the possibility of destruction without remainder. We know from De la grammatology, any trace, any archive, is erasable. In «No
Apocalypse, not now» Derrida writes that «the absolute catastrophe which
would irreversibly destroy the total archive and any symbolic capacity, the
very “survival” at the heart of life» would destroy at the same time «any
symbolic capacity[7]», that
is to say any possibility of interiorizing the lost, any possibility of grief
as introjection and idealization.
Therefore, any life always lives in the shadow of this threat, the
threat of having to accept grief as the very dispossession of the capacity to
mourn to accept this terrible thing, at the limit of the unthinkable, truly ungraspable,
that grief be a decision of the other.
As we can see, death as paradoxical condition of survival is
a plural death. Firstly, in that we must
die several times to ourselves in order to survive interiorizing these
deaths. Secondly, in that the
possibility of these integrated or comprehended sacrifices runs up against the
incomprehensible, the wholly other as it resists symbol, and thus
sacrifice. More than one death, more
than one grief.
Second motif, the delay. This motif is articulated in «Demeure, Athènes» around
what «to take» [prendre] a photograph can signify. By way of response, Derrida shows how the
phrase «We owe ourselves to death» imposed itself
upon him as a photograph, a snapshot.
We owe ourselves to death…[This sentence] caught me, it surprised
me, (as if it had photographed me without me noticing)…it overtook me, perhaps
like death, a death which should have found me, there where I still hid myself,
it entrusted me with I don’t know what, myself perhaps, and perhaps us, it was
especially trusting in me, allowing me an advance. It granted me an advance … With regard to
this advance, I was not only owing but late. Under final notice of restitution.[8]
Death imposes itself from the origin, in the manner of a snapshot,
without history, without precondition, «a negative without origin[9]»,
taking on the spot any living being, like a time bomb, overtaking life even
though it has only begun, opening the countdown or the final notice. This «law of immanence» is too, from the beginning, always pluralized. First, in that there is more than one delay
in the delay, where all the temporalities of life do not all mark the same
time; we advance there, we withdraw elsewhere.
Yet the delay multiplies itself also in another sense. Such as one comes to illustrate it, the delay
is that which Heidegger characterizes as the relation that the mortal maintains
with his own end; it is a matter of the existential delay or
being-towards-death.
Yet,
Derrida had hardly invoked «being-and-time
in its Greek tradition […], from the epigraph of the Sophist to the opening of Being
and Time[10]» when he disaggregates
and de-solitarizes in some way the delay of the final
notice from this delay in question, that is to
say of the delay which opens to Dasein
its future. There
would be a delay older than this existential delay.
A delay older than any «mine-ness (Jemeinigkeit)» of dying,
older than the phrase «my death». It
would date from before Dasein. As we saw in examining the first motif, the possibility of an impossible
grief is in some manner more originary than that of grief as process of
interiorization, as condition of survival.
As Derrida shows in Aporias,
all begins by grief:
«If Jemeinigkeit, that of Dasein or that of the ego[…] is
constituted in its ipseity on the basis of an originary grief, than this
self-relation welcomes or supposes the other within its being-itself as
different from the self. And
reciprocally, the relation to the other (in
itself outside myself, outside of myself in myself), is never distinguished from a bereaved apprehension[11]».
Therefore, an irreducible difference of self to self comes to
dislodge the possessive in the utterance «my death». There is, before MY death, not the death of
the other, but the other of my death,
that is to say the impossibility of taking
[prendre] death for my own. More
than one death. More than one retard.
Third motif: the anticipation of the deadline and the
calculation of the instant of death. Evoking cape Sounion in « Demeure, Athènes »,
Derrida recalls that it is from this cape that Socrates saw his death
come. When the boat returning from the
pilgrimage to Delos would be in sight off the coast of this cape, the day and
hour of his death would be decreed. Crito says to Socrates that, in all
likelihood, the boat will arrive at the port that very day. Yet Socrates responds that in a dream he saw
a woman who predicted that he would die but the following day.
Socrates, Derrida
says, «owes the ability to calculate the instant of his death to a dream[12].» First pluralization of the times of
anticipation: the calculation of the deadline made possible by the dream frustrates, differing by a day, the
calculation made by Crito and those that come from Sounion. A phantasmatic anticipation
comes to loge itself at the heart of a reasonable anticipation, which predicts
the most likely and yet again delays the verdict. Everything occurs as if a certain clock
signed the irreducible “mineness” of dying, by calculating the moment according
to another temporality than that of the social clocks. Everything occurs as if
this slight discrepancy, from one day to the other, from one date to the other,
already marked in Platonic philosophy, the difference that Heidegger will draw
out in Being and Time between the
phenomenon of my death, which
properly belongs to Dasein and the «one dies», banality of death for the community of men. Even when the sentence to death is certain
and there is nothing left but to wait, never can my death coincide with the
death, with this event that everyone expects.
The decree of death does not exempt Dasein
from having to die its own death, from owing itself to its death, this is what makes the impossible
possibility of death. One anticipation
is always behind or ahead of the other.
The decree of death, in the sense of condemnation, of juridical
sentence, can never take, never capture my
death. At the very
center of its ineluctable character, death remains ungraspable.
This is the lesson of the «discipline of
death», of l’epimeleia tou thanatou, the vigil the soul holds for
itself. This vigil is never contemporaneous with the final hour or the final
night. This is one of the senses that
the phrase «We owe ourselves to death» can take: We must take care to
respect disjointed, pluralized time, which disturbs the unity and the unicity
of the fatal instant.
However «We owe
ourselves to death» refers also to another pluralization. Derrida declares, «the exercise, the care or
the discipline of death, [...] have nothing to do [despite the “irresistible
analogies with it”] I am sure, with the verdict “we owe ourselves to death” — a
phrase which could even say the contrary[13].»
Indeed the ungraspable, irreducibly surprising,
character of death prevents anyone from ever predicting the late arrival to death. It is impossible not to expect death,
but it concerns an expectation «without
horizon of expectation», which suspends any calculation. In the Socratic tradition of the discipline
of death, the phrase, «we owe ourselves to
death» signifies «we must
dedicate ourselves to death, we have duties towards it, it is necessary to
devote our meditations, our cares, our attentions, our exercises, our
discipline to it [...] We must devote ourselves to the death to which we are
destined etcetera[14].» Yet Derrida adds: «this
is not the only sense that my phrase holds. And I protested tacitly against
it». This protest has its source in the
incalculable, precisely there where it is impossible to devote yourself to the deadline,
because one can never see it come. There
would be, in the horizon of expectation itself, a blind spot, a resistance to
the calculation and to the plot of destiny or of history. And this residue, this remainder, this
resistance, remains and resists in us, in each of us, in this secret place
which reveals to us that there is more than one us in us. One which calculates and believes he
anticipates, the other which delays, which does
not see and will never see anything come, an us held back, which does not know how to tell time and does not take [prendre] care of itself. More than one death. More than one anticipation.
This duplication of
the “us” leads me to the fourth and final
motif. Let us examine this
duplication in the doubling of the us visible in the phrase «Nous nous devons à
la mort», «We owe ourselves to death»:
What I would like to suggest would be, in short, the following: the
first us, the «subject», would come after the
second one (the reflecting object, the one taken in view, and which begins to look
at us from over there, like a «photographed
object»). It
would constitute itself as «subject» only after having reflected the «second» us, which is itself constituted as an «object» due or owed. «We» are «due» (moratorium, delay,
final notice), we appear to ourselves, we relate to ourselves, we take
ourselves in view as what is due, taken by a debt or a duty which precedes us
and institutes us, a debt which contracts us before we have even contracted it.[15]
An us lagging behind the other. The
subject, in us, would be the retroactive, reflective operation, which would
calculate what it owes to the a-subjectivizable.
Who, one will ask,
is this «us»? An additional
pluralization will appear. Again. Who is this us? «The first us who watches, observes and
photographs the other, and who speaks here, it is an innocent living being who
forever ignores death: in this us we
are infinite... [16]».
We are infinite. This can be understood as «we are
countless». It is impossible to close
the count of the us in us, to understand it, to take it, to grasp it, to
collect it.
Yet this can be
understood also, and this second sense meets in some manner the first, as «we are
not finite», we, at least a certain we in we, are not finite, we have nothing to do with finitude. We die but are not concerned with
finitude. We are an innocent living
being, acquitted of finitude. What does
this mean?
It concerns here a
critical reference to Heidegger who reserves death, inseparable for him from
«to properly die», for Dasein,
distinguishing it from «to perish», verenden,
reserved for the animal. The animal, the
living animal, does not die, it perishes.
In this sense, one cannot speak of animal finitude, since the animal
does not have a being-towards-death, it does not have time, it does not
maintain any relation to its end, it can see nothing come. For Heidegger, « the difference between a
mortal, (one who dies in the sense of “to properly die”) and an animal
incapable of dying, is a certain access to death as death, to death as such,
[which conditions] any distinction between these two ends that are to perish
and to die, and at the same time the
very possibility of an analytic of Dasein
and another mode of being[17] ».
This Heideggerian
distinction inscribes, at the same time, immortality in
the living being, the animal cannot die, and imperishability in Dasein, Dasein cannot perish. There is in us, in each of us and in each
us—they are infinite—an innocent living being, who does not calculate, who does
not see death come, who does not walk freely towards it, who does not
anticipate, who does not have an end in this sense. And this us remains forever ungraspable. More
than one death. More than mortality in
death.
The list of these
plurals could lengthen still, we are truly in the countless here. I should make do with insisting again on the
fact that to pluralize death and being-towards-death, truly comes down to
pushing philosophy to its limit. For
what becomes of philosophy from the moment when the mortal, who has always been
thought of as the unique addressor and the unique addressee of philosophy,
witnesses the very dislocation of his being? This question is timely.
The hypothesis of
the total destruction of the archive, which has continuously accompanied me
here, is indeed the very matter at hand.
It belongs to an age which is, as Derrida shows in « No Apocalypse, not now », the nuclear
age. The possibility of nuclear war,
which appears only in the twentieth century, is truly—and it is the first time
in history—the actual, not phantasmed possibility of a destruction of the world
without remainder, and we can henceforth, only think on the basis of this
threat. It is this that is impossible to
anticipate, it is this that dooms us to an impossible grief, it is this that
exceeds being-towards-death. Yet, as at
the same time, this destruction has not occurred, as it has not happened, it has
none other but a textual
referent. It has no other referent than
the discourses that we hold on its subject.
We can only speak of it, and therefore its referent is nothing real,
existing or present, it is constituted by textuality itself.
This structure of
textual referentiality, in order to be made manifest by a specific period in or
our history, has at the same time no age, it has been at work from the origin. Death, mortality are themselves precisely
without referents other than textual.
Textual, that is to say non-being, non-existent, consisting simply
in the production of traces. Our age,
the nuclear age, acts therefore only to reveal, to open an arresting view on
that which has always waited to be unconcealed, the ungraspability of death itself, and of the mortal. To insist on the textuality of the referent,
is truly to open, at the heart of subjectivity, a space that is irreducible to
it. The mortal can give meaning to his
mortality, without referent, only in producing traces of it, his entire life is
thus the trace of this wholly other in him.
A wholly other which divides him, forever prevents him from gathering
together, engages him in the infinite game of a difference with one’s self that
cannot synthesize.
This then is what is
essential: the deconstructed subject is the one who is no longer charged with
making sense by way of syntheses. The
ungraspable, in us, is that which is dispersed, released from the burden of synthesis.
Here the question
surely, again and always, is that of the structure of the erasability of the
trace. Every trace is susceptible to
fading. Any trace is likely to fade, and
it is truly this possibility of erasure that upholds all analysis of plural
death. It is the trace that renders grief
impossible, which lags behind the origin, which does not appear, which severs
and splits the us. Indeed, if this more
than one death in death, this more than one us in us, does not gather together,
remains fundamentally and irreducible ungraspable, how can they inscribe
themselves, other than in erasing or crossing themselves out?
Derrida insists
quite frequently on the fact that the structure «ni…ni»
«neither… nor»--neither this nor that—the aporetic structure par excellence is the only one adequate to
characterize this dispersal of the subject and the pluralization which follows
from it. The aporetic structure, neither this nor that,
thus takes precedence over the structure of co-implication or synthesis, of the
model at the same time this and
that. If there is more than one death in
death, one cannot say that death is at the same time this, that, etcetera. Its faces are precisely not co-implicative. A subject not implicated, not complicated, by
the plurality of deaths within it or by the plurality of subjects in it, is it
still a subject? Is it still even mortal?
In a sense, one might consider that the trace, as it does not implicate
itself in, as it does not scheme with synthesis, as it does not let itself be
caught, is never there where one believes it, does not let itself be
approached, and that it is in fact indefatigable, enduring, inexhaustibly
mobile and transposable. Derrida
himself, in Points of Suspension,
speaks of the «indefatigable contradiction of the double bind [18]». One could think that an indefatigable, a tireless trace, always in a sense young, like a
compulsion for repetition, which would escape all logic of habit, is precisely
not an indelible trace. Yet it is truly
necessary to see that the trace, in Derrida, is always susceptible to betraying
(itself) [de (se) faire faux bond], this susceptibility being the exact
condition of fatigue, of deterioration, which finish by taking to the death all
the subjects that are dying in us. One
cannot die otherwise than of and by betrayal.
Translated by Simone Rowen
[1] Derrida, Jacques « The Time is out of joint », in
Anselm Haverkamp (ed.) Decon-struction is/in America. A New Sense of the
Political, New York, New York University Press, 1995, p. 17.
[2] Jacques Derrida, « La Mythologie Blanche», in Marges — de la philosophie, Paris,
Minuit, coll. « Critique », 1972, p. 323.
[3] Derrida, Jacques.
« Demeure, Athènes (Nous nous devons à la mort) », in Athènes à l’ombre de l’Acropole, photography by Jean-François
Bonhomme, Athènes, Olkos, 1996. We will refer from hereon directly to this text
by designating it by the initial D, followed by the page number.
[7] Derrida, Jacques. «No Apocalypse, not now», in Psyché. Inventions de l’autre, Paris,
Galilée, coll. «La philosophie en effet », 1987, p. 379.
[9] D, 44.
[10] D, 44.
[12] D, 58.
[14] D, 61.
[15] D, 61-62.
[16] D, 63.
[17] D, 70.
[18] Derrida, Jacques, Points de suspension. Entretiens. Paris,
Galilée, coll. « La philosophie en effet », 1992, p
.69.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)